module Category.limits where
Limits are an abstract structure that captures and generalizes concepts such as products and coproducts, pullbacks and equalizers.
An indexed family of sets is a collection of objects where each object is labeled with an object from an index set. For example, say X is a set of \(x_i\)’s with each \(x_i\) labeled with an integer \(i\), so \(x_1, x_2 ... x_n ∈ X\). Another way to look at them is to say an indexed family is a function which when given an index returns a member of X, i.e. it is a function that takes an \(i\) and returns an \(x_i\): \(f : i → x_i\).
A diagram is a categorical analogue of indexed families. Informally, a diagram in a category ℂ consists of some objects of ℂ connected by some morphisms of ℂ all indexed by a fixed category.
Formally, an indexed category ℂ indexed over a category \(\mathcal{S}\) is defined by a functor:
\[ ℂ : \mathcal{S}^{op} → Cat \]
where Cat
is the category of categories (a 2-category) and \(\mathcal{S}\) can be thought of as the analogue of the set i
for indexed sets.
If \(\mathcal{S}\) has a terminal object *
we think of \(ℂ\) as the underlying ordinary category of the \(\mathcal{S}\)-indexed category ℂ.
A diagram takes an indexed category \(\mathcal{J}\) and maps it to a category ℂ:
\(D : \mathcal{J} → ℂ\)
The diagram D is thought of as indexing a collection of objects and morphisms in C patterned on J, which is usually a very small category. This permits us to single out and study repeating patterns or subgraphs of a category. Diagrams permit further structures:
The limit of a diagram D, denoted by \(\lim D\) is a cone (A, η) to D such that for every other cone (B, ψ) there exists a unique morphism \(u : A → B\) such that \(η_X ∘ u = ψ_X\) for all X in D. Limits are thus a universal construction. Diagrams may have limits, when they do the limits are essentially unique. This category theoretic notion does represent the same notion in analysis (limits in the context of calculus).
Let \(F : D^{op} \to C\) be a functor. If the limit \(\lim F \in C\) of F exist, then it singles out a special cone given by the composite morphism
\(*→*↦Id limFHom C(limF,limF)→≃Hom(pt,Hom(limF,F(−)))\)
where the first morphism picks the identity morphism on limFF and the second one is the defining bijection of a limit as above.
The cone is called the universal cone over F.
Here are some important examples of limits, classified by the shape of the diagram: