Contents Previous Next


Rules of introduction of types

module Types.patterns where

open import Lang.dataStructures using (List; _::_; [])
open import Types.product using (Σ; _,_; fst; snd; __; inj₁; inj₂)

There is a general pattern for introduction of a new kind of type in type theory. To specify a type, we specify:

Formation

We start with describing what are the rules to follow when creating an instance of the type being introduced. It is a “type-constructor-level” law.

For example we introduce natural numbers like:

data Nat : Set where
  zero : Nat
  succ : Nat  Nat

Functions’ from A → B have formation rules of the types A and B to exist. Similarly, products (A × B) depend upon the existence of types A and B and so do co-product types A ∪ B.

Constructor / Introduction

We then proceed to define how an element of the new type could be constructed. For natural numbers, zero and succ are the constructors:

one = succ zero
two = succ one
three = succ two

Function types can be described by their implementation using lambda abstraction:

f : A → B ≡ λ A . B

Products have the constructor , to create product types, so do coproducts have the inj₁ and inj₂ constructors.

Elimination

Next we describe how to consume or make use of elements of this type.

Since Nat is an inductive type, its eliminator is inductive as well. In fact, for a natural number, an eliminator is any proposition P that can use a natural number. This is proved by assuming P zero and some proof of inductively deducing P (succ k) given P (k) and using them to prove P n:

Nat-elim : (P : Nat  Set)
         P zero
         ((k : Nat)  P k  P (succ k))
         (n : Nat)
         P n
Nat-elim P p proof zero = p
Nat-elim P p proof (succ n) = proof n (Nat-elim P p proof n)

For function types, function application are the elimination rules.

For products the elimination rules are the rules for extracting each element from a product, in other words, fst and snd. For coproducts, the eliminator is also an extractor where one has to explain what to do in either case A or B pops out using maybe.

Computation

Computation rules describe how an eliminator acts on a constructor. For natural numbers:

Nat-comp₀ : (P : Nat  Set)
         P zero
         ((k : Nat)  P k  P (succ k))
         P zero
Nat-comp₀ P p proof = Nat-elim P p proof zero

Nat-comp : (P : Nat  Set)
         P zero
         ((k : Nat)  P k  P (succ k))
         (n : Nat)
         P (succ n)
Nat-comp P p proof n = Nat-elim P p proof (succ n)

For function types, $ (λx.Φ)(a) ≡ substitute(a, x.Φ) $, i.e. the function is equal to substituting a for every occurrence of x. For products, the computation rule boils down to $ f : A × B → C ≡ A → B → C $, also called currying.

Uniqueness principle

Finally the uniqueness principle describes how functions to and from the new type are unique. For some types the uniqueness principle behaves as the dual of the computation rule by describing how constructors act on eliminators. For other types the uniqueness principle implies conditions under which functions from the new type are unique.

TODO


Equational Reasoning